Consciousness And Theory Of Mind - pediagenosis
Article Update
Loading...

Friday, July 26, 2019

Consciousness And Theory Of Mind


Consciousness And Theory Of Mind
In this chapter we discuss what is meant by consciousness, and how this can be altered in certain pathological conditions. This ability to be aware of what we are doing, namely consciousness, is then discussed further in terms of how we can understand the thought processes of others, so-called theory of mind, disorders of which may underlie a range of conditions, especially autism.


Consciousness And Theory Of Mind, Consciousness – what is it?, Consciousness and theory of mind, Vegetative state,

Consciousness – what is it?
In thinking about consciousness, it is important to differentiate between the level and the content of conscious experience. The level of consciousness may also be referred to as the level of arousal while the contents of consciousness refers to the objects and occurrences of which we are aware. Of course, the contents of consciousness will be affected greatly by the level of consciousness but these two phenomena are likely to be at least partly dissociable. For example, people in hyperaroused states may be less aware of surroundings than less-aroused individuals. Conversely, it has recently been shown that individuals in a vegetative state may actually show neurophysiological patterns of activity (as measured by functional magnetic resonance imaging [fMRI]; see Chapter 53), indicating a much richer level of awareness than their immobile unresponsive state would suggest.
In general, experimental and clinical access to the contents of consciousness relies on verbal report and certain behavioural indicators. We may ask a subject to tell us or to indicate whether they are aware of a stimulus in the periphery of their visual field. We may assess their memory by requiring them to indicate whether they have an awareness of a particular stimulus that was previously presented to them. We may also attempt to ascertain the richness of their awareness through such measures; with respect to memory, for example, does the subject truly recollect a prior presentation or do they simply have a strong sense that it is familiar? An important observation with respect to the contents of consciousness is that while our awareness obviously defines our experience of the world, the explanations that they provide for our behaviour is only partial and may be inaccurate. This was shown strikingly in an experiment by Libet and colleagues, who required volunteers to make periodic movements while simultaneously recording cerebral activity. They showed that subjective assessments of becoming aware of an intention to move actually occurred some 500 ms after there had been a brain response. This finding, subsequently replicated, suggests that our brain can indicate what we are about to do before we are aware of wanting to do it.
Further evidence of a discrepancy between what we are aware of and what we actually do comes from work by Castiello and colleagues. These authors showed that when subjects receive incorrect feedback about the trajectory of an arm movement that they are in the process of making, they will correct the movement without actually being aware of doing so, even when the correction made is relatively large. Furthermore, when asked to reproduce the movement that they have just made, subjects will reproduce the one that mirrors the incorrect feedback that they were given, further suggesting that they were unconscious of the control that they have exerted over the movement.
It is also the case that previously experienced events or objects may influence our ongoing actions and decisions without necessarily re-emerging into consciousness. The occurrence of basic processing outside our awareness would seem to be an efficient way of freeing our conscious processing to deal with more complex problems. However, it should be remembered that there are clear instances where the contents of consciousness may have a marked impact on lower level processes. For example, Haggard and colleagues showed that subjects who have made a willed (conscious) movement are likely to link more closely in time that movement with an outcome than when the movement is not felt to be consciously initiated (if it is produced by application of a brief magnetic field over the motor cortex).
Thus, consciousness enables actions to gain greater prominence in our memory, but much of what we do routinely does not require this to happen. As to the precise neurobiological origin of con- sciousness, this is unknown, but the coordinated activity of the cortex and its reciprocal connections to the thalamus and diffusely projecting brainstem nuclei is important. This is best illustrated in patients in a vegetative state (see below) and blindsight (see Chapter 26). In this latter condition there is damage to the primary visual cortex such that individuals cannot consciously see but when tested it is clear that their visual system can detect stimuli of different forms including colour and motion. It is thought to arise from the intact extrastriate visual areas, which cannot feedback to the primary visual cortex, as a result of which conscious visual perception is lost.

Consciousness and theory of mind
As humans, we may be unique in being conscious of our conscious- ness. This “thinking about thinking” has been referred to as ‘meta representation’ and it is perhaps the ability to represent our own mental states and those of others that facilitates and shapes our most complex social interactions. To be able to represent the mental states of others has been referred to as having a theory of mind. We use this theory of mind to interpret, explain and predict many of the actions and utterances of other people. If someone is being sarcastic or deceitful, they say and do precisely the opposite of what they feel. By understanding these possibilities their behaviour may become more logical and predictable to us.
What happens if we have difficulty with theory of mind processing? It has been suggested that the isolation and very limited social repertoire of individuals with autism may arise from the difficulty that they have in understanding the mental states of other people. There is also evidence that people with schizophrenia may have deficits in theory of mind abilities and in both cases the abnormality underlying this deficit is thought to reside in the prefrontal cortex (see Chapter 34).

Vegetative state
Some patients who have a major global brain injury (e.g. anoxia secondary to a cardiac or respiratory arrest) can end up in a state of unresponsive wakefulness or a vegetative state (which is said to be permanent if it continues for more than six months to a year depending on the nature of the original insult). In this state the patient clearly has periods of sleep and wakefulness, but during the latter time they are unable to respond to any stimuli as there is extensive damage above the level of the arousal systems in the brainstem. In some cases the responses to such stimuli are present, but inconsistently so, and such individuals are deemed to be in a minimally conscious state (MCS).
It is important that all individuals in a vegetative state or MCS are investigated thoroughly over time using a range of stimuli and functional imaging (see Chapter 53). This is because although some patients appear not to be able to respond there is evidence of cortical activation with sensory stimuli on functional imaging. In these cases, the patient may have had a more focal injury to the upper brainstem that prevents them from being able to make any clear motor responses to stimuli – the so-called locked-in syndrome. Once diagnosed, such patients may be able to communicate through the use of eye movements and blinking (see Chapter 56).

Share with your friends

Give us your opinion

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.

Notification
This is just an example, you can fill it later with your own note.
Done